Hinweise zur Catholic Encyclopedia
Teaching of St. Augustine of Hippo
St. Augustine of Hippo (354-430) is a philosophical and theological genius
of the first order, dominating, like a pyramid, antiquity and the succeeding
ages. Compared with the great philosophers of past centuries and modern times,
he is the equal of them all; among theologians he is undeniably the first, and
such has been his influence that none of the Fathers, Scholastics, or Reformers
has surpassed it.
(Philip Schaff, History of the Christian Church) Elsewhere,
we have discussed his life and his writings; here, we shall treat of his
teaching and influence in three sections:
I. His Function as a Doctor of the Church
II. His System of Grace
III. Augustinism in History
I. HIS FUNCTION AS A DOCTOR OF THE CHURCH
When the critics endeavour to determine Augustine's place in the history of
the Church and of civilization, there can be no question of exterior or
political influence, such as was exercised by St. Leo, St. Gregory, or St.
Bernard. As Reuter justly observes, Augustine was bishop of a third-rate city
and had scarcely any direct control over politics, and Harnack adds that perhaps
he had not the qualifications of a statesman. If Augustine occupies a place
apart in the history of humanity, it is as a thinker, his influence being felt
even outside the realm of theology, and playing a most potent part in the
orientation of Western thought. It is now universally conceded that, in the
intellectual field, this influence is unrivalled even by that of Thomas Aquinas,
and Augustine's teaching marks a distinct epoch in the history of Christian
thought. The better to emphasize this important fact we shall try to determine:
(1) the rank and degree of influence that must be ascribed to Augustine;
(2) the nature, or the elements, of his doctrinal influence;
(3) the general qualities of his doctrine; and
(4) the character of his genius.
(1) The greatest of the Doctors
It is first of all a remarkable fact that the great critics, Protestant as
well as Catholic, are almost unanimous in placing St. Augustine in the foremost
rank of Doctors and proclaiming him to be the greatest of the Fathers. Such,
indeed, was also the opinion of his contemporaries, judging from their
expressions of enthusiasm gathered by the Bollandists. The popes attributed such
exceptional authority to the Doctor of Hippo that, even of late years, it has
given rise to lively theological controversies. Peter the Venerable accurately
summarized the general sentiment of the Middle Ages when he ranked Augustine
immediately after the Apostles; and in modern times Bossuet, whose genius was
most like that of Augustine, assigns him the first place among the Doctors, nor
does he simply call him the incomparable Augustine, but the Eagle of Doctors
,
the Doctor of Doctors.
If the Jansenistic abuse of his works and perhaps the
exaggerations of certain Catholics, as well as the attack of Richard Simon, seem
to have alarmed some minds, the general opinion has not varied. In the
nineteenth century Stöckl expressed the thought of all when he said, Augustine
has justly been called the greatest Doctor of the Catholic world.
And the admiration of Protestant critics is not less enthusiastic. More than
this, it would seem as if they had in these latter days been quite specially
fascinated by the great figure of Augustine, so deeply and so assiduously have
they studied him (Bindemann, Schaff, Dorner, Reuter, A. Harnack, Eucken, Scheel,
and so on) and all of them agree more or less with Harnack when he says: Where,
in the history of the West, is there to be found a man who, in point of
influence, can be compared with him?
Luther and Calvin were content to treat
Augustine with a little less irreverence than they did the other Fathers, but
their descendants do him full justice, although recognizing him as the Father of
Roman Catholicism. According to Bindemann, Augustine is a star of extraordinary
brilliancy in the firmament of the Church. Since the apostles he has been
unsurpassed.
In his History of the Church
Dr. Kurtz calls Augustine the
greatest, the most powerful of all the Fathers, him from whom proceeds all the
doctrinal and ecclesiastical development of the West, and to whom each recurring
crisis, each new orientation of thought brings it back.
Schaff himself (Saint
Augustine, Melanchthon and Neander, p. 98) is of the same opinion: While most
of the great men in the history of the Church are claimed either by the Catholic
or by the Protestant confession, and their influence is therefore confined to
one or the other, he enjoys from both a respect equally profound and enduring
.
Rudolf Eucken is bolder still, when he says: On the ground of Christianity
proper a single philosopher has appeared and that is Augustine.
The English
Miter, W. Cunningham, is no less appreciative of the extent and perpetuity of
this extraordinary influence: The whole life of the medieval Church was framed
on lines which he has suggested: its religious orders claimed him as their
patron; its mystics found a sympathetic tone in his teaching; its polity was to
some extent the actualization of his picture of the Christian Church; it was in
its various parts a carrying out of ideas which he cherished and diffused. Nor
does his influence end with the decline of medievalism: we shall see presently
how closely his language was akin to that of Descartes, who gave the first
impulse to and defined the special character of modern philosophy.
And after
having established that the doctrine of St. Augustine was at the bottom of all
the struggles between Jansenists and Catholics in the Church of France, between
Arminians and Calvinists on the side of the Reformers, he adds: And once more
in our own land when a reaction arose against rationalism and Erastinianism it
was to the African Doctor that men turned with enthusiasm: Dr. Pusey's edition
of the Confessions was among the first-fruits of the Oxford Movement.
But Adolf Harnack is the one who has oftenest emphasized the unique rôle of
the Doctor of Hippo. He has studied Augustine's place in the history of the
world as reformer of Christian piety and his influence as Doctor of the Church.
In his study of the Confessions
he comes back to it: No man since Paul is
comparable to him
- with the exception of Luther, he adds. - Even today we
live by Augustine, by his thought and his spirit; it is said that we are the
sons of the Renaissance and the Reformation, but both one and the other depend
upon him.
(2) Nature and different aspects of his doctrinal influence
This influence is so varied and so complex that it is difficult to consider
under all its different aspects. First of all, in his writings the great bishop
collects and condenses the intellectual treasures of the old world and transmits
them to the new. Harnack goes so far as to say: It would seem that the
miserable existence of the Roman empire in the West was prolonged until then,
only to permit Augustine's influence to be exercised on universal history.
It
was in order to fulfil this enormous task that Providence brought him into
contact with the three worlds whose thought he was to transmit: with the Roman
and Latin world in the midst of which he lived, with the Oriental world
partially revealed to him through the study of Manichæism, and with the Greek
world shown to him by the Platonists. In philosophy he was initiated into the
whole content and all the subtilties of the various schools, without, however,
giving his allegiance to any one of them. In theology it was he who acquainted
the Latin Church with the great dogmatic work accomplished in the East during
the fourth century and at the beginning of the fifth; he popularized the results
of it by giving them the more exact and precise form of the Latin genius.
To synthesis of the past, Augustine adds the incomparable wealth of his own thought, and he may be said to have been the most powerful instrument of Providence in development and advance of dogma. Here the danger has been not in denying, but in exaggerating, this advance. Augustine's dogmatic mission (in a lower sphere and apart from inspiration) recalls that of Paul in the preaching of the Gospel. It has also been subject to the same attacks and occasioned the same vagaries of criticism. Just as it was sought to make of Paulinism the real source of Christianity as we know it - a system that had smothered the primitive germ of the Gospel of Jesus - so it was imagined that, under the name of Augustinianism, Augustine had installed in the Church some sort of syncretism of the ideas of Paul and of neo-Platonism which was a deviation from ancient Christianity, fortunate according to some, but according to others utterly deplorable. These fantasies do not survive the reading of the texts, and Harnack himself shows in Augustine the heir to the tradition that preceded him. Still, on the other hand, his share of invention and originality in the development of dogma must not be ignored, although here and there, on special questions, human weaknesses crop out. He realized, better than any of the Fathers, the progress so well expressed by Vincent of Lérins, his contemporary, in a page that some have turned against him.
In general, all Christian dogmatics are indebted to him for new theories that
better justify and explain revelation, new views, and greater clearness and
precision. The many struggles with which he was identified, together with the
speculative turn of his mind, brought almost every question within the scope of
his research. Even his way of stating problems so left his impress upon them
that there Is no problem, one might almost say, in considering which the
theologian does not feel the study of Augustine's thought to be an imperative
obligation. Certain dogmas in particular he so amply developed, so skilfully
unsheathing the fruitful germ of the truths from their envelope of tradition,
that many of these dogmas (wrongly, in our opinion) have been set down as
Augustinism
. Augustine was not their inventor, he was only the first to put
them in a strong light. They are chiefly the dogmas of the Fall, the Atonement,
Grace, and Predestination. Schaff (op. cit. 97) has very properly said: His
appearance in the history of dogma forms a distinct epoch, especially as regards
anthropological and soteriological doctrines, which he advanced considerably
further, and brought to a greater clearness and precision, than they had ever
had before in the consciousness of the Church.
But he is not only the Doctor of
Grace, he is also the Doctor of the Church: his twenty years' conflict with
Donatism led to a complete exposition of the dogmas of the Church, the great
work and mystical Body of Christ, and true Kingdom of God, of its part in
salvation and of the intimate efficacy of its sacraments. It is on this point,
as the very centre of Augustinian theology, that Reuter has concentrated those
Augustinische Studien
which, according to Harnack, are the most learned of
recent studies on St. Augustine. Manichæan controversies also led him to state
clearly the great questions of the Divine Being and of the nature of evil, and
he might also be called the Doctor of Good, or of good principles of all things.
Lastly, the very idiosyncrasy of his genius and the practical, supernatural, and
Divine imprint left upon all his intellectual speculations have made him the
Doctor of Charity.
Another step forward due to the works of Augustine is in the language of
theology, for, if he did not create it, he at least contributed towards its
definite settlement. It is indebted to him for a great number of epigrammatic
formulæ, as significant as they are terse, afterwards singled out and adopted by
Scholasticism. Besides, as Latin was more concise and less fluid in its forms
than Greek, it was wonderfully well suited to the work. Augustine made it the
dogmatic language par excellence, and Anselm, Thomas Aquinas, and others
followed his lead. At times he has even been credited with the pseudo-Athanasian
creed which is undoubtedly of later date, but those critics were not mistaken
who traced its inspiration to the formulæ in De Trinitate.
Whoever its author
may have been, he was certainly familiar with Augustine and drew upon his works.
It is unquestionably this gift of concise expression, as well as his charity,
that has so often caused the celebrated saying to be attributed to him: In
essentials unity, in non-essentials liberty, in all things charity.
Augustine stands forth, too, as the great inspirer of religious thought in
subsequent ages. A whole volume would not be sufficient to contain the full
account of his influence on posterity; here we shall merely call attention to
its principal manifestations. It is, in the first place, a fact of paramount
importance that, with St. Augustine, the centre of dogmatic and theological
development changed from East to West. Hence, from this view-point again, he
makes an epoch in the history of dogma. The critics maintain that up to his time
the most powerful influence was exerted by the Greek Church, the East having
been the classic land of theology, the great workshop for the elaboration of
dogma. From the time of Augustine, the predominating influence seems to emanate
from the West, and the practical, realistic spirit of the Latin race supplants
the speculative and idealistic spirit of Greece and the East. Another fact, no
less salient, is that it was the Doctor of Hippo who, in the bosom of the Church,
inspired the two seemingly antagonistic movements, Scholasticism and Mysticism.
From Gregory the Great to the Fathers of Trent, Augustine's theological
authority, indisputably the highest, dominates all thinkers and is appealed to
alike by the Scholastics Anselm, Peter Lombard, and Thomas Aquinas, and by
Bernard, Hugh of St. Victor, and Tauler, exponents of Mysticism, all of whom
were nourished upon his writings and penetrated with his spirit. There is not
one of even the most modern tendencies of thought but derives from him whatever
it may have of truth or of profound religious sentiment. Learned critics, such
as Harnack, have called Augustine the first modern man,
and in truth, he so
moulded the Latin world that it is really he who has shaped the education of
modern minds. But, without going so far, we may quote the German philosopher,
Eucken: It is perhaps not paradoxical to say that if our age wishes to take up
and treat in an independent way the problem of religion, it is not so much to
Schleiermacher or Kant, or even Luther or St. Thomas, that it must refer, as to
Augustine. … And outside of religion, there are points upon which Augustine is
more modern than Hegel or Schopenhauer.
(3) The dominating qualities of his doctrine
The better to understand St. Augustine's influence, we must point out in his doctrine certain general characteristics which must not be lost sight of, if, in reading his works, one would avoid troublesome misapprehensions.
First, the full development of the great Doctor's mind was progressive. It
was by stages, often aided by the circumstances and necessities of controversy,
that he arrived at the exact knowledge of each truth and a clean-cut perception
of its place in the synthesis of revelation. He also requires that his readers
should know how to advance with him.
It is necessary to study St. Augustine's
works in historical order and, as we shall see, this applies particularly to the
doctrine of grace.
Augustinian doctrine is, again, essentially theological, and has God for its
centre. To be sure Augustine is a great philosopher, and Fénelon said of him:
If an enlightened man were to gather from the books of St. Augustine the
sublime truths which this great man has scattered at random therein, such a
compendium [extrait], made with discrimination, would be far superior to
Descartes' Meditations.
And indeed just such a collection was made by the
Oratorian ontologist, André Martin. There is then a philosophy of St. Augustine,
but in him philosophy is so Intimately coupled with theology as to be
inseparable from it. Protestant historians have remarked this characteristic of
his writings. The world,
says Eucken, interests him less than
the action of
God in the world and especially in ourselves. God and the soul are the only
subjects the knowledge Of which ought to fire us with enthusiasm. All knowledge
becomes moral, religious knowledge, or rather a moral, religious conviction, an
act of faith on the part of man, who gives himself up unreservedly. And with
still greater energy Böhringer has said: The axis on which the heart, life and
theology of Augustine move is God.
Oriental discussions on the Word had forced
Athanasius and the Greek Fathers to set faith in the Word and in Christ, the
Saviour, at the very summit of theology; Augustine, too, in his theology, places
the Incarnation at the centre of the Divine plan, but he looks upon it as the
great historic manifestation of God to humanity - the idea of God dominates all:
of God considered in His essence (On the Trinity), in His government (The City
of God) or as the last end of all Christian life (Enchiridion and On the
Christian Combat).
Lastly, Augustine's doctrine bears an eminently Catholic stamp and is
radically opposed to Protestantism. It is important to establish this fact,
principally because of the change in the attitude of Protestant critics towards
St. Augustine. Indeed, nothing is more deserving of attention than this
development so highly creditable to the impartiality of modern writers. The
thesis of the Protestants of olden times is well known. Attempts to monopolize
Augustine and to make him an ante-Reformation reformer, were certainly not
wanting. Of course Luther had to admit that he did not find in Augustine
justification by faith alone, that generating principle of all Protestantism;
and Schaff tells us that he consoled himself with exclaiming (op. sit., p. 100):
Augustine has often erred, he is not to be trusted. Although good and holy, he
was yet lacking in true faith as well as the other Fathers.
But in general, the
Reformation did not so easily fall into line, and for a long time it was
customary to oppose the great name of Augustine to Catholicism. Article 20 of
the Confession of Augsburg dares to ascribe to him justification without works,
and Melanchthon invokes his authority in his Apologia Confessionis.
In the
last thirty or forty years all has been changed, and the best Protestant critics
now vie with one another in proclaiming the essentially Catholic character of
Augustinian doctrine. In fact they go to extremes when they claim him to be the
founder of Catholicism. It is thus that H. Reuter concludes his very important
studies on the Doctor of Hippo: I consider Augustine the founder of Roman
Catholicism in the West….This is no new discovery, as Kattenbusch seems to
believe, but a truth long since recognized by Neander, Julius Köstlin, Dorner,
Schmidt, … etc.
Then, as to whether Evangelicalism is to be found in
Augustine, he says: Formerly this point was reasoned out very differently from
what it is nowadays. The phrases so much in use from 1830 to 1870: Augustine is
the Father of evangelical Protestantism and Pelagius is the Father of
Catholicism, are now rarely met with. They have since been acknowledged to be
untenable, although they contain a particula veri.
Philip Schaff reaches the
same conclusion; and Dorner says, It is erroneous to ascribe to Augustine the
ideas that inspired the Reformation.
No one, however, has put this idea in a
stronger light than Harnack. Quite recently, in his 14th lesson on The Essence
of Christianity,
he characterized the Roman Church by three elements, the third
of which is Augustinism, the thought and the piety of St. Augustine. In fact
Augustine has exerted over the whole inner life of the Church, religious life
and religious thought, an absolutely decisive influence.
And again he says, In
the fifth century, at the hour when the Church inherited the Roman Empire, she
had within her a man of extraordinarily deep and powerful genius: from him she
took her ideas, and to this present hour she has been unable to break away from
them.
In his History of Dogma
(English tr., V, 234, 235) the same critic
dwells at length upon the features of what he calls the popular Catholicism
to
which Augustine belongs. These features are (a) the Church as a hierarchical
institution with doctrinal authority; (b) eternal life by merits, and disregard
of the Protestant thesis of salvation by faith
- that is, salvation by that
firm confidence in God which the certainty of pardon produces (c) the
forgiveness of sins - in the Church and the Church; (d) the distinction between
commands and counsel - between grievous sine and venial sins - the scale of
wicked men and good men - the various degrees of happiness in heaven according
to one's deserts; (e) Augustine is accused of outdoing the superstitious ideas
of this popular Catholicism - the infinite value of Christ's satisfaction,
salvation considered as enjoyment of God in heaven - the mysterious efficacy of
the sacraments (ex opere operato) - Mary's virginity even in childbirth - the
idea of her purity and her conception, unique in their kind. Harnack does not
assert that Augustine taught the Immaculate Conception, but Schaff (op. cit., p.
98) says unhesitatingly: He is responsible also for many grievous errors of the
Roman Church … he anticipated the dogma of the immaculate conception of the
Virgin Mary, and his ominous word, Roma locuta est, causa finite est, might
almost be quoted in favour of the Vatican decree of papal infallibility.
Nevertheless, it were a mistake to suppose that modern Protestants relinquish
all claim upon Augustine; they will have it that, despite his essential
Catholicism, it was he who inspired Luther and Calvin. The new thesis, therefore,
is that each of the two Churches may claim him in turn. Burke's expression
quoted by Schaff (ibid., p. 102) is characteristic: In Augustine ancient and
modern ideas are melted and to his authority the papal Church has as much right
to appeal as the Churches of the Reformation.
No one notes this contradiction
more clearly than Loofs. After stating that Augustine has accentuated the
characteristic elements of Western (Catholic) Christianity, that in succeeding
ages he became its Father, and that the Ecclesiasticism of Roman Catholicism,
Scholasticism, Mysticism, and even the claims of the papacy to temporal rule,
are founded upon a tendency initiated by him,
Loofs also affirms that he is the
teacher of all the reformers and their bond of union, and concludes with this
strange paradox: The history of Catholicism is the history of the progressive
elimination of Augustinism.
The singular aptitude of these critics for
supposing the existence of flagrant contradictions in a genius like Augustine is
not so astonishing when we remember that, with Reuter, they justify this theory
by the reflection: In whom are to be found more frequent contradictions than in
Luther?
But their theories are based upon a false interpretation of Augustine's
opinion, which is frequently misconstrued by those who are not sufficiently
familiar with his language and terminology.
(4) The character of his genius
We have now to ascertain what is the dominating quality which accounts for
his fascinating influence upon posterity. One after another the critics have
considered the various aspects of this great genius. Some have been particularly
impressed by the depth and originality of his conceptions, and for these
Augustine is the great sower of the ideas by which future minds are to live.
Others, like Jungmann and Stöckl, have praised in him the marvellous harmony of
all the mind's higher qualities, or, again, the universality and the compass of
his doctrine. In the great African Doctor,
says the Rev. J. A. Zahm (Bible,
Science and Faith, Fr. tr., 56), we seem to have found united and combined the
powerful and penetrating logic of Plato, the deep scientific conceptions of
Aristotle, the knowledge and intellectual suppleness of Origen, the grace and
eloquence of Basil and Chrysostom. Whether we consider him as philosopher, as
theologian, or as exegetist…he still appears admirable the unquestioned Master
of all the centuries.
Philip Schaff (op. cit., p. 97) admires above all such a
rare union of the speculative talent of the Greek and of the practical spirit of
the Latin Church as he alone possessed.
In all these opinions there is a great
measure of truth; nevertheless we believe that the dominating characteristic of
Augustine's genius and the true secret of his influence are to be found in his
heart - a heart that penetrates the most exalted speculations of a profound mind
and animates them with the most ardent feeling. It is at bottom only the
traditional and general estimate of the saint that we express; for he has always
been represented with a heart for his emblem, just as Thomas Aquinas with a sun.
Mgr. Bougaud thus interpreted this symbol: Never did man unite in one and the
same soul such stern rigour of logic with such tenderness of heart.
This is
also the opinion of Harnack, Böhringer, Nourisson, Storz, and others. Great
intellectuality admirably fused with an enlightened mysticism is Augustine's
distinguishing characteristic. Truth is not for him only an object of
contemplation; it is a good that must be possessed, that must be loved and lived
by. What constitutes Augustine's genius is his marvellous gift of embracing
truth with all the fibres of his soul; not with the heart alone, for the heart
does not think; not with the mind alone, for the mind grasps only the abstract
or, as it were, lifeless truth. Augustine seeks the living truth, and even when
he is combating certain Platonic ideas he is of the family of Plato, not of
Aristotle. He belongs indisputably to all ages because he is in touch with all
souls, but he is preeminently modern because his doctrine is not the cold light
of the School; he is living and penetrated with personal sentiment. Religion is
not a simple theory, Christianity is not a series of dogmas; It Is also a life,
as they say nowadays, or, more accurately, a source of life. However, let us not
be deceived. Augustine is not a sentimentalist, a pure mystic, and heart alone
does not account for his power. If in him the hard, cold intellectuality of the
metaphysician gives place to an impassioned vision of truth, that truth is the
basis of it all. He never knew the vaporous mysticism of our day, that allows
itself to be lulled by a vague, aimless sentimentalism. His emotion is deep,
true, engrossing, precisely because it is born of a strong, secure, accurate
dogmatism that wishes to know what it loves and why it loves. Christianity is
life, but life in the eternal, unchangeable truth. And if none of the Fathers
has put so much of his heart into his writings, neither has any turned upon
truth the searchlight of a stronger, clearer intellect.
Augustine's passion is characterized not by violence, but by a communicative
tenderness; and his exquisite delicacy experiences first one and then another of
the most intimate emotions and tests them; hence the irresistible effect of the
Confessions
. Feuerlein, a Protestant thinker, has brought out in relief
(exaggeratedly, to be sure, and leaving the marvellous powers of his intellect
in the shade) Augustine's exquisite sensibility - what he calls the feminine
elements
of his genius. He says: It was not merely a chance or accidental part
that his mother, Monica, played in his intellectual development, and therein
lies what essentially distinguishes him from Luther, of whom it was said:
Everything about him bespeaks the man
. And Schlösser, whom Feuerlein quotes,
is not afraid to say that Augustine's works contain more genuine poetry than all
the writings of the Greek Fathers. At least it cannot be denied that no thinker
ever caused so many and such salutary tears to flow. This characteristic of
Augustine's genius explains his doctrinal work. Christian dogmas are considered
in relation to the soul and the great duties of Christian life, rather than to
themselves and in a speculative fashion. This alone explains his division of
theology in the Enchiridion,
which at first sight seems so strange. He
assembles all Christian doctrine in the three theological virtues, considering
in the mysteries the different activities of the soul that must live by them.
Thus, in the Incarnation, he assigns the greatest part to the moral side, to the
triumph of humility. For this reason, also, Augustine's work bears an imprint,
until then unknown, of living personality peeping out everywhere. He inaugurates
that literature in which the author's individuality reveals itself in the most
abstract matters, the Confessions
being an inimitable example of it. It is in
this connection that Harnack admires the African Doctor's gift of psychological
observation and a captivating facility for portraying his penetrating
observations. This talent, he says, is the secret of Augustine's originality and
greatness. Again, it is this same characteristic that distinguishes him from the
other Doctors and gives him his own special temperament. The practical side of a
question appealed to the Roman mind of Ambrose, too, but he never rises to the
same heights, nor moves the heart as deeply as does his disciple of Milan.
Jerome is a, more learned exegetist, better equipped in respect of Scriptural
erudition; he is even purer in his style; but, despite his impetuous ardour, he
is less animated, less striking, than his correspondent of Hippo. Athanasius,
too, is subtile in the metaphysical analysis of dogma, but he does not appeal to
the heart and take hold of the soul like the African Doctor. Origen played the
part of initiator in the Eastern Church, just as Augustine did in the Western,
but his influence, unfortunate in more ways than one, was exercised rather in
the sphere of speculative intelligence, while that of Augustine, owing to the
qualities of his heart, extended far beyond the realm of theology. Bossuet, who
of all geniuses most closely resembles Augustine by his elevation and his
universality, is his superior in the skilfulness and artistic finish of his
works, but he has not the alluring tenderness of soul; and if Augustine
fulminates less, he attracts more powerfully, subjugating the mind with
gentleness.
Thus may Augustine's universal influence in all succeeding ages be explained:
it is due to combined gifts of heart and mind. Speculative genius alone does not
sway the multitude; the Christian world, apart from professional theologians,
does not read Thomas Aquinas. On the other hand, without the clear, definite
idea of dogma, mysticism founders as soon as reason awakes and discovers the
emptiness of metaphors: this is always the fate of vague pietism, whether it
recognize Christ or not, whether It be extolled by Schleiermacher, Sabatier, or
their disciples. But to Augustine's genius, at once enlightened and ardent, the
whole soul is accessible, and the whole Church, both teachers and taught, is
permeated by his sentiments and ideas. A. Harnack, more than any other critic,
admires and describes Augustine's influence over all the life of Christian
people. If Thomas Aquinas is the Doctor of the Schools, Augustine is, according
to Harnack, the inspirer and restorer of Christian piety. If Thomas inspires the
canons of Trent, Augustine, besides having formed Thomas himself, inspires the
inner life of the Church and is the soul of all the great reforms effected
within its pale. In his Essence of Christianity
(14th lesson, 1900, p. 161)
Harnack shows how Catholics and Protestants live upon the piety of Augustine.
His living has been incessantly relived in the course of the fifteen hundred
years that have followed. Even to our days interior and living piety among
Catholics, as well as the mode of its expression, has been essentially
Augustinian: the soul is permeated by his sentiment, it feels as he felt and
rethinks his thoughts. It is the same with many Protestants also, and they are
by no means among the worst. And even those to whom dogma is but a relic of the
past proclaim that Augustine's influence will live forever.
This genuine emotion is also the veil that hides certain faults from the
reader or else makes him oblivious of them. Says Eucken: Never could Augustine
have exercised all the influence he has exercised if it had not been that, in
spite of the rhetorical artifice of his utterance, absolute sincerity reigned in
the inmost recesses of his soul.
His frequent repetitions are excused because
they are the expression of his deep feeling. Schaff says: His books, with all
the faults and repetitions of isolated parts, are a spontaneous outflow from the
marvellous treasures of his highly-gifted mind and his truly pious heart.
(St.
Augustine, p. 96.) But we must also acknowledge that his passion is the source
of exaggerations and at times of errors that are fraught with real danger for
the inattentive or badly disposed reader. Out of sheer love for Augustine
certain theologians have endeavoured to justify all he wrote, to admire all, and
to proclaim him infallible, but nothing could be more detrimental to his glory
than such excess of praise. The reaction already referred to arises partly from
this. We must recognize that the passion for truth sometimes fixes its attention
too much upon one side of a complex question; his too absolute formulæ, lacking
qualification, false in appearance now in one sense now in another. The
oratorical temperament that was his in such a high degree,
says Becker, very
truly (Revue d'histoire ecclésiastique, 15 April, 1902, p. 379), the kind of
exaltation that befitted his rich imagination and his loving soul, are not the
most reliable in philosophical speculations.
Such is the origin of the
contradictions alleged against him and of the errors ascribed to him by the
predestinarians of all ages. Here we see the rôle of the more frigid minds of
Scholasticism. Thomas Aquinas was a necessary corrective to Augustine. He is
less great, less original, and, above all, less animated; but the calm didactics
of his intellectualism enable him to castigate Augustine's exaggerations with
rigorous criticism, to impart exactitude and precision to his terms - in one
word, to prepare a dictionary with which the African Doctor may be read without
danger.
II. HIS SYSTEM OF GRACE
It is unquestionably in the great Doctor's solution of the eternal problem of freedom and grace - of the part taken by God and by man, in the affair of salvation - that his thought stands forth as most personal, most powerful, and most disputed. Most personal, for he was the first of all to synthesize the great theories of the Fall, grace, and free will; and moreover it is he who, to reconcile them all, has furnished us with a profound explanation which is in very truth his, and of which we can find no trace in his predecessors. Hence, the term Augustinism is often exclusively used to designate his system of grace. Most powerful, for, as all admit, it was he above all others who won the triumph of liberty against the Manichæans, and of grace against the Pelagians. His doctrine has, in the main, been solemnly accepted by the Church, and we know that the canons of the Council of Orange are borrowed from his works. Most disputed, also. Like St. Paul, whose teachings he develops, he has often been quoted, often not understood. Friends and enemies have exploited his teaching in the most diverse senses. It has not been grasped, not only by the opponents of liberty, and hence by the Reformers of the sixteenth century, but even today, by Protestant critics the most opposed to the cruel predestinationism of Calvin and Luther who father that doctrine on St. Augustine. A technical study would be out of place here; it will be sufficient to enunciate the most salient thoughts, to enable the reader to find his bearings.
(1) It is regarded as incontestable today that the system of Augustine was
complete in his mind from the year 397 - that is, from the beginning of his
episcopate, when he wrote his answers to the quæstiones Diversæ
of Simplician.
It is to this book that Augustine, in his last years, refers the Semipelagians
for the explanation of his real thought. This important fact, to which for a
long time no attention was paid, has been recognized by Neander and established
by Gangaut, and also by recent critics, such as Loofs, Reuter, Turmel, Jules
Martin (see also Cunningham, St. Austin, 1886, pp. 80 and 175). It will not,
therefore, be possible to deny the authority of these texts on the pretext that
Augustine in his old age adopted a system more antagonistic to liberty.
(2) The system of Pelagius can today be better understood than heretofore.
Pelagius doubtless denied original sin, and the immortality and integrity of
Adam; in a word, the whole supernatural order. But the parent idea of his system,
which was of stoic origin, was nothing else than the complete emancipation
of
human liberty with regard to God, and its limitless power for good and for evil.
It depended on man to attain by himself, without the grace of God, a stoic
impeccability and even insensibility, or the absolute control of his passions.
It was scarcely suspected, even up to our time, what frightful rigorism resulted
from this exaggeration of the powers of liberty. Since perfection was possible,
it was of obligation. There was no longer any distinction between precepts and
counsels. Whatever was good was a duty. There was no longer any distinction
between mortal and venial sin. Every useless word merited hell, and even
excluded from the Church the children of God. All this has been established by
hitherto unedited documents which Caspari has published (Briefe, Abhandlungen,
und Predigten, Christiania, 1890).
(3) The system of St. Augustine in opposition to this rests on three fundamental principles:
- God is absolute Master, by His grace, of all the determinations of the will;
- man remains free, even under the action of grace;
- the reconciliation of these two truths rests on the manner of the Divine government.
Absolute sovereignty of God over the will
This principle, in opposition to the emancipation of Pelagius, has not always been understood in its entire significance. We think that numberless texts of the holy Doctor signify that not only does every meritorious act require supernatural grace, but also that every act of virtue, even of infidels, should be ascribed to a Gift of God, not indeed to a supernatural grace (as Baius and the Jansenists pretend), but to a specially efficacious providence which has prepared this good movement of the will (Retractations, I, ix, n. 6). It is not, as theologians very wisely remark, that the will cannot accomplish that act of natural virtue, but it is a fact that without this providential benefit it would not. Many misunderstandings have arisen because this principle has not been comprehended, and in particular the great medieval theology, which adopted it and made it the basis of its system of liberty, has not been justly appreciated. But many have been afraid of these affirmations which are so sweeping, because they have not grasped the nature of God's gift, which leaves freedom intact. The fact has been too much lost sight of that Augustine distinguishes very explicitly two orders of grace: the grace of natural virtues (the simple gift of Providence, which prepares efficacious motives for the will); and grace for salutary and supernatural acts, given with the first preludes of faith. The latter is the grace of the sons, gratia fliorum; the former is the grace of all men, a grace which even strangers and infidels (filii concubinarum, as St. Augustine says) can receive (De Patientiâ, xxvii, n. 28).
Man remains free, even under the action of grace
The second principle, the affirmation of liberty even under the action of
efficacious grace, has always been safeguarded, and there is not one of his
anti-Pelagian works even of the latest, which does not positively proclaim a
complete power of choice in man; not but what it does not depend on the free
choice of the will to embrace the faith or reject it, but in the elect this will
is prepared by God
(De Prædest. SS., n. 10). The great Doctor did not reproach
the Pelagians with requiring a power to choose between good and evil; in fact he
proclaims with them that without that power there is no responsibility, no merit,
no demerit; but he reproaches them with exaggerating this power. Julian of
Eclanum, denying the sway of concupiscence, conceives free will as a balance in
perfect equilibrium. Augustine protests: this absolute equilibrium existed in
Adam; it was destroyed after original sin; the will has to struggle and react
against an inclination to evil, but it remains mistress of its choice (Opus
imperfectum contra Julianum, III, cxvii). Thus, when he says that we have lost
freedom in consequence of the sin of Adam, he is careful to explain that this
lost freedom is not the liberty of choosing between good and evil, because
without it we could not help sinning, but the perfect liberty which was calm and
without struggle, and which was enjoyed by Adam in virtue of his original
integrity.
The reconciliation of these two truths
But is there not between these two principles an irremediable antinomy? On the one hand, there is affirmed an absolute and unreserved power in God of directing the choice of our will, of converting every hardened sinner, or of letting every created will harden itself; and on the other hand, it is affirmed that the rejection or acceptance of grace or of temptation depends on our free will. Is not this a contradiction? Very many modern critics, among whom are Loofs and Harnack, have considered these two affirmations as irreconcilable. But it is because, according to them, Augustinian grace is an irresistible impulse given by God, just as in the absence of it every temptation inevitably overcomes the will. But in reality all antinomy disappears if we have the key of the system; and this key is found in the third principle: the Augustinian explanation of the Divine government of wills, a theory so original, so profound, and yet absolutely unknown to the most perspicacious critics, Harnack, Loofs, and the rest.
Here are the main lines of this theory: The will never decides without a motive, without the attraction of some good which it perceives in the object. Now, although the will may be free in presence of every motive, still, as a matter of fact it takes different resolutions according to the different motives presented to it. In that is the whole secret of the influence exercised, for instance, by eloquence (the orator can do no more than present motives), by meditation, or by good reading. What a power over the will would not a man possess who could, at his own pleasure, at any moment, and in the most striking manner, present this or the other motive of action? - But such is God's privilege. St. Augustine has remarked that man is not the master of his first thoughts; he can exert an influence on the course of his reflections, but he himself cannot determine the objects, the images, and, consequently, the motives which present themselves to his mind. Now, as chance is only a word, it is God who determines at His pleasure these first perceptions of men, either by the prepared providential action of exterior causes, or interiorly by a Divine illumination given to the soul. - let us take one last step with Augustine: Not only does God send at His pleasure those attractive motives which inspire the will with its determinations, but, before choosing between these illuminations of the natural and the supernatural order, God knows the response which the soul, with all freedom, will make to each of them. Thus, in the Divine knowledge, there is for each created will an indefinite series of motives which de facto (but very freely) win the consent to what is good. God, therefore, can, at His pleasure, obtain the salvation of Judas, if He wishes, or let Peter go down to perdition. No freedom, as a matter of fact, will resist what He has planned, although it always keeps the power of going to perdition. Consequently, it is God alone, in His perfect independence, who determines, by the choice of such a motive or such an inspiration (of which he knows the future influence), whether the will is going to decide for good or for evil. Hence, the man who has acted well must thank God for having sent him an inspiration which was foreseen to be efficacious, while that favour has been denied to another. A fortiori, every one of the elect owes it to the Divine goodness alone that he has received a series of graces which God saw to be infallibly, though freely, bound up with final perseverance.
Assuredly we may reject this theory, for the Church, which always maintains the two principles of the absolute dependence of the will and of freedom, has not yet adopted as its own this reconciliation of the two extremes. We may ask where and how God knows the effect of these graces. Augustine has always affirmed the fact; he has never inquired about the mode; and it is here that Molinism has added to and developed his thoughts, in attempting to answer this question. But can the thinker, who created and until his dying day maintained this system which is so logically concatenated, be accused of fatalism and Manichæism?
It remains to be shown that our interpretation exactly reproduces the thought
of the great Doctor. The texts are too numerous and too long to be reproduced
here. But there is one work of Augustine, dating from the year 397, in which he
clearly explains his thought - a work which he not only did not disavow later
on, but to which in particular he referred, at the end of his career, those of
his readers who were troubled by his constant affirmation of grace. For example,
to the monks of Adrumetum who thought that liberty was irreconcilable with this
affirmation, he addressed a copy of this book De Diversis quæstionibus ad
Simplicianum,
feeling sure that their doubts would be dissipated. There, in
fact, he formulates his thoughts with great clearness. Simplician had asked how
he should understand the Epistle to the Romans 9, on the predestination of Jacob
and Esau. Augustine first lays down the fundamental principle of St. Paul, that
every good will comes from grace, so that no man can take glory to himself for
his merits, and this grace is so sure of its results that human liberty will
never in reality resist it, although it has the power to do so. Then he affirms
that this efficacious grace is not necessary for us to be able to act well, but
because, in fact, without it we would not wish to act well. From that arises the
great difficulty: How does the power of resisting grace fit in with the
certainty of the result? And it is here that Augustine replies: There are many
ways of inviting faith. Souls being differently disposed, God knows what
invitation will be accepted, what other will not be accepted. Only those are the
elect for whom God chooses the invitation which is foreseen to be efficacious,
but God could convert them all: Cujus autem miseretur, sic cum vocat, quomodo
scit ei congruere ut vocantem non respuat
(op. cit., I, q. ii, n. 2, 12, 13).
Is there in this a vestige of an irresistible grace or of that impulse
against which it is impossible to fight, forcing some to good, and others to sin
and hell? It cannot be too often repeated that this is not an idea flung off in
passing, but a fundamental explanation which if not understood leaves us in the
impossibility of grasping anything of his doctrine; but if it is seized
Augustine entertains no feelings of uneasiness on the score of freedom. In fact
he supposes freedom everywhere, and reverts incessantly to that knowledge on
God's part which precedes predestination, directs it, and assures its infallible
result. In the De Done perseverantiæ
(xvii, n. 42), written at the end of his
life, he explains the whole of predestination by the choice of the vocation
which is foreseen as efficacious. Thus is explained the chief part attributed to
that external providence which prepares, by ill health, by warnings, etc., the
good thoughts which it knows will bring about good resolutions. Finally, this
explanation alone harmonizes with the moral action which he attributes to
victorious grace. Nowhere does Augustine represent it as an irresistible impulse
impressed by the stronger on the weaker. It is always an appeal, an invitation
which attracts and seeks to persuade. He describes this attraction, which is
without violence, under the graceful image of dainties offered to a child, green
leaves offered to a sheep (In Joannem, tract. xxvi, n. 5). And always the
infallibility of the result is assured by the Divine knowledge which directs the
choice of the invitation.
(4) The Augustinian predestination presents no new difficulty if one has understood the function of this Divine knowledge in the choice of graces. The problem is reduced to this: Does God in his creative decree and, before any act of human liberty, determine by an immutable choice the elect and the reprobate? - Must the elect during eternity thank God only for having rewarded their merits, or must they also thank Him for having, prior to any merit on their part, chosen them to the meriting of this reward? One system, that of the Semipelagians, decides in favour of man: God predestines to salvation all alike, and gives to all an equal measure of grace; human liberty alone decides whether one is lost or saved; from which we must logically conclude (and they really insinuated it) that the number of the elect is not fixed or certain. The opposite system, that of the Predestinationists (the Semipelagians falsely ascribed this view to the Doctor of Hippo), affirms not only a privileged choice of the elect by God, but at the same time (a) the predestination of the reprobate to hell and (b) the absolute powerlessness of one or the other to escape from the irresistible impulse which drags them either to good or to evil. This is the system of Calvin.
Between these two extreme opinions Augustine formulated (not invented) the Catholic dogma, which affirms these two truths at the same time:
- the eternal choice of the elect by God is very real, very gratuitous, and constitutes the grace of graces;
- but this decree does not destroy the Divine will to save all men, which, moreover, is not realized except by the human liberty that leaves to the elect full power to fall and to the non-elect full power to rise.
Here is how the theory of St. Augustine, already explained, forces us to conceive of the Divine decree: Before all decision to create the world, the infinite knowledge of God presents to Him all the graces, and different series of graces, which He can prepare for each soul, along with the consent or refusal which would follow in each circumstance, and that in millions and millions of possible combinations. Thus He sees that if Peter had received such another grace, he would not have been converted; and if on the contrary such another Divine appeal had been heard in the heart of Judas, he would have done penance and been saved. Thus, for each man in particular there are in the thought of God, limitless possible histories, some histories of virtue and salvation, others of crime and damnation; and God will be free in choosing such a world, such a series of graces, and in determining the future history and final destiny of each soul. And this is precisely what He does when, among all possible worlds, by an absolutely free act, He decides to realize the actual world with all the circumstances of its historic evolutions, with all the graces which in fact have been and will be distributed until the end of the world, and consequently with all the elect and all the reprobate who God foresaw would be in it if de facto He created it.
Now in the Divine decree, according to Augustine, and according to the Catholic Faith on this point, which has been formulated by him, the two elements pointed out above appear:
- The certain and gratuitous choice of the elect - God decreeing, indeed, to create the world and to give it such a series of graces with such a concatenation of circumstances as should bring about freely, but infallibly, such and such results (for example, the despair of Judas and the repentance of Peter), decides, at the same time, the name, the place, the number of the citizens of the future heavenly Jerusalem. The choice is immutable; the list closed. It is evident, indeed, that only those of whom God knows beforehand that they will wish to co-operate with the grace decreed by Him will be saved. It is a gratuitous choice, the gift of gifts, in virtue of which even our merits are a gratuitous benefit, a gift which precedes all our merits. No one, in fact, is able to merit this election. God could, among other possible worlds, have chosen one in which other series of graces would have brought about other results. He saw combinations in which Peter would have been impenitent and Judas converted. It is therefore prior to any merit of Peter, or any fault of Judas, that God decided to give them the graces which saved Peter and not Judas. God does not wish to give paradise gratuitously to any one; but He gives very gratuitously to Peter the graces with which He knows Peter will be saved. - Mysterious choice! Not that it interferes with liberty, but because to this question: Why did not God, seeing that another grace would have saved Judas, give it to him? Faith can only answer, with Augustine: O Mystery! O Altitudo! (De Spiritu et litterâ, xxxiv, n. 60).
- But this decree includes also the second element of the Catholic dogma: the
very sincere will of God to give to all men the power of saving themselves and
the power of damning themselves. According to Augustine, God, in his creative
decree, has expressly excluded every order of things in which grace would
deprive man of his liberty, every situation in which man would not have the
power to resist sin, and thus Augustine brushes aside that predestinationism
which has been attributed to him. Listen to him speaking to the Manichæans:
All can be saved if they wish
; and in hisRetractations
(I, x), far from correcting this assertion, he confirms it emphatically:It is true, entirely true, that all men can, if they wish.
But he always goes back to the providential preparation. In his sermons he says to all:It depends on you to be elect
(In Ps. cxx, n. 11, etc.);Who are the elect? You, if you wish it
(In Ps. Lxxiii, n. 5). But, you will say, according to Augustine, the lists of the elect and reprobate are closed. Now if the non-elect can gain heaven, if all the elect can be lost, why should not some pass from one list to the other? You forget the celebrated explanation of Augustine: When God made His plan, He knew infallibly, before His choice, what would be the response of the wills of men to His graces. If, then, the lists are definitive, if no one will pass from one series to the other, it is not because anyone cannot (on the contrary, all can), it is because God knew with infallible knowledge that no one would wish to. Thus I cannot effect that God should destine me to another series of graces than that which He has fixed, but, with this grace, if I do not save myself it will not be because I am not able, but because I do not wish to.
Such are the two essential elements of Augustinian and Catholic
predestination. This is the dogma common to all the schools, and formulated by
all theologians: predestination in its entirety is absolutely gratuitous (ante
merita). We have to insist on this, because many have seen in this immutable and
gratuitous choice only a hard thesis peculiar to St. Augustine, whereas it is
pure dogma (barring the mode of conciliation, which the Church still leaves
free). With that established, the long debates of theologians on special
predestination to glory ante or post merita are far from having the importance
that some attach to them. (For a fuller treatment of this subtile problem see
the Dict. de théol. cath., I, coll. 2402 sqq.) I do not think St. Augustine
entered that debate; in his time, only dogma was in question. But it does not
seem historically permissible to maintain, as many writers have, that Augustine
first taught the milder system (post merita), up to the year 416 (In Joan.
evang., tract. xii, n. 12) and that afterwards, towards 418, he shifted his
ground and went to the extreme of harsh assertion, amounting even to
predestinationism. We repeat, the facts absolutely refute this view. The ancient
texts, even of 397, are as affirmative and as categorical as those of his last
years, as critics like Loofs and Reuter have shown. If, therefore, it is shown
that at that time he inclined to the milder opinion, there is no reason to think
that he did not persevere in that sentiment.
(5) The part which Augustine had in the doctrine of Original Sin has been brought to light and determined only recently.
In the first place, It is no longer possible to maintain seriously, as was formerly the fashion (even among certain Catholics, like Richard Simon), that Augustine invented in the Church the hitherto unknown doctrine of original sin, or at least was the first to introduce the idea of punishment and sin. Dorner himself (Augustinus, p. 146) disposed of this assertion, which lacks verisimilitude. In this doctrine of the primal fall Augustine distinguished, with greater insistency and clearness than his predecessors, the punishment and the sin - the chastisement which strips the children of Adam of all the original privileges - and the fault, which consists in this, that the crime of Adam, the cause of the fall is, without having been committed personally by his children, nevertheless in a certain measure imputed to them, in virtue of the moral union established by God between the head of the human family and his descendants.
To pretend that in this matter Augustine was an innovator, and that before him the Fathers affirmed the punishment of the sin of Adam in his sons, but did not speak of the fault, is a historical error now proved to demonstration. We may discuss the thought of this or that pre Augustinian Father, but, taking them as a whole, there is no room for doubt. The Protestant R. Seeberg (Lehrbuch der Dogmengeschichte, I, p. 256), after the example of many others, proclaims it by referring to Tertullian, Commodian, St. Cyprian, and St. Ambrose. The expressions, fault, sin, stain (culpa, peccatum, macula) are repeated in a way to dispel all doubt. The truth is that original sin, while being sin, is of a nature essentially different from other faults, and does not exact a personal act of the will of the children of Adam in order to be responsible for the fault of their father, which is morally imputed to them. Consequently, the Fathers - the Greeks especially - have insisted on its penal and afflictive character, which is most in evidence, while Augustine was led by the polemics of the Pelagians (and only by them) to lay emphasis on the moral aspect of the fault of the human race in its first father.
With regard to Adam's state before the fall Augustine not only affirmed,
against Pelagius, the gifts of immortality, impassibility, integrity, freedom
from error, and, above all, the sanctifying grace of Divine adoption, but he
emphasized its absolutely gratuitous and supernatural character. Doubtless,
considering the matter historically and de facto, it was only the sin of Adam
that inflicted death on us - Augustine repeats it again and again - because God
had safeguarded us against the law of our nature. But de jure neither
immortality nor the other graces were our due, and Augustine recognized this in
affirming that God could have made the condition in which we were actually born
the primitive condition of our first parents. That assertion alone is the very
reverse of Jansenism. It is, moreover, formally confirmed in the Retractations
(I, ix, n. 6).
(6) Does this mean that we must praise everything in St. Augustine's explanation of grace? Certainly not. And we shall note the improvements made by the Church, through her doctors, in the original Augustinism. Some exaggerations have been abandoned, as, for instance, the condemnation to hell of children dying without baptism. Obscure and ambiguous formulæ have been eliminated. We must say frankly that Augustine's literary method of emphasizing his thought by exaggerated expressions, issuing in troublesome paradoxes, has often obscured his doctrine, aroused opposition in many minds, or led them into error. Also, it is above all important, in order to comprehend his doctrine, to compile an Augustinian dictionary, not a priori, but after an objective study of his texts. The work would be long and laborious, but how many prejudices it would dispel!
The Protestant historian Ph. Schaff (St. Augustine, p. 102) writes: The
great genius of the African Church, from whom the Middle Ages and the
Reformation have received an impulse alike powerful, though in different
directions, has not yet fulfilled the work marked out for him in the counsels of
Divine Wisdom. He serves as a bond of union between the two antagonistic
sections of Western Christendom, and encourages the hope that a time may come
when the injustice and bitterness of strife will be forgiven and forgotten, and
the discords of the past be drowned forever in the sweet harmonies of perfect
knowledge and perfect love.
May this dream be realized!
III. AUGUSTINISM IN HISTORY
The influence of the Doctor of Hippo has been so exceptional in the Church,
that, after having indicated its general characteristics (see above), it is
proper to indicate the principal phases of the historical development of his
doctrine. The word Augustinism designates at times the entire group of
philosophical doctrines of Augustine, at others, it is restricted to his system
of grace. Hence,
(1) philosophical Augustinism;
(2) theological Augustinism on grace;
(3) laws which governed the mitigation of Augustinism.
(1) Philosophical Augustinism
In the history of philosophical Augustinism we may distinguish three very
distinct phases. First, the period of its almost exclusive triumph in the West,
up to the thirteenth century. During the long ages which were darkened by the
invasion of the barbarians, but which were nevertheless burdened with the
responsibility of safeguarding the sciences of the future, we may say that
Augustine was the Great Master of the West. He was absolutely without a rival,
or if there was one, it was one of his disciples, Gregory the Great, who, after
being formed in his school, popularized his theories. The rôle of Origen, who
engrafted neo-Platonism on the Christian schools of the East, was that of
Augustine in the West, with the difference, however, that the Bishop of Hippo
was better able to detach the truths of Platonism from the dreams of Oriental
imagination. Hence, a current of Platonic ideas was started which will never
cease to act upon Western thought. This influence shows itself in various ways.
It is found in the compilers of this period, who are so numerous and so well
deserving of recognition - such as Isidore, Bede, Alcuin - who drew abundantly
from the works of Augustine, just as did the preachers of the sixth century, and
notably St. Cæsarius. In the controversies, especially in the great disputes of
the ninth and twelfth centuries on the validity of Simoniacal ordinations, the
text of Augustine plays the principal part. Carl Mirbt has published on this
point a very interesting study: Die Stellung Augustins in der Publizistik des
gregorianischen Kirchenstreits
(Leipzig, 1888). In the pre-Thomistic period of
Scholasticism, then in process of formation, namely, from Anselm to Albert the
Great, Augustine is the great inspirer of all the masters, such as Anselm,
Abelard, Hugo of St. Victor, who is called by his contemporaries, another
Augustine, or even the soul of Augustine. And it is proper to remark, with
Cunningham (Saint Austin, p. 178), that from the time of Anselm the cult of
Augustinian ideas exercised an enormous influence on English thought in the
Middle Ages. As regards Peter Lombard, his Sentences are little else than an
effort to synthesize the Augustinian theories.
While they do not form a system as rigidly bound together as Thomism, yet Father Mandonnet (in his learned study of Siger de Brabant) and M. de Wulf (on Gilles de Lessines) have been able to group these theories together. And here let us present a summary sketch of those theses regarded in the thirteenth century as Augustinian, and over which the battle was fought. First, the fusion of theology and philosophy; the preference given to Plato over Aristotle - the latter representing rationalism, which was mistrusted, whilst the idealism of Plate exerted a strong attraction - wisdom regarded rather as the philosophy of the Good than the philosophy of the True. As a consequence, the disciples of Augustine always have a pronounced tinge of mysticism, while the disciples of St. Thomas may be recognized by their very accentuated intellectualism. In psychology the illuminating and immediate action of God is the origin of our intellectual knowledge (at times it is pure ontologism); and the faculties of the soul are made substantially identical with the soul itself. They are its functions, and not distinct entities (a thesis which was to keep its own partisans in the Scholasticism of the future and to be adopted by Descartes); the soul is a substance even without the body, so that after death, it is truly a person. In cosmology, besides the celebrated thesis of rationes seminales, which some have recently attempted to interpret in favour of evolutionism, Augustinism admitted the multiplicity of substantial forms in compound beings, especially in man. But especially in the impossibility of creation ab æterno, or the essentially temporal character of every creature which is subject to change, we have one of the ideas of Augustine which his disciples defended with greater constancy and, it would appear, with greater success.
A second period of very active struggles came in the thirteenth century, and
this has only lately been recognized. Renan (Averroes, p. 259) and others
believed that the war against Thomism, which was just then beginning, was caused
by the infatuation of the Franciscans for Averroism; but if the Franciscan Order
showed itself on the whole opposed to St. Thomas, it was simply from a certain
horror at philosophical innovations and at the neglect of Augustinism. The
doctrinal revolution brought about by Albert the Great and Thomas Aquinas in
favour of Aristotle startled the old School of Augustinism among the Dominicans
as well as among the Franciscans, but especially among the latter, who were the
disciples of the eminent Augustinian doctor, St. Bonaventure. This will explain
the condemnations, hitherto little understood, of many propositions of St.
Thomas Aquinas three years after his death, on the 7th of March, 1277, by the
Bishop of Paris, and on the 18th of March, 1277, by the Archbishop of Canterbury,
Robert Kilwardby, a Dominican. The Augustinian school represented tradition;
Thomism, progress. The censure of 1277 was the last victory of a too rigid
Augustinism. The happy fusion of the two methods in the two orders of
Franciscans and Dominicans little by little brought about an agreement on
certain points without excluding differences on others which were yet obscure
(as, for instance, the unity or the multiplicity of forms), at the same time
that it made for progress in all the schools. We know that the canonization of
St. Thomas caused the withdrawal of the condemnations of Paris (14 February,
1325). Moreover, the wisdom or the moderation of the new school contributed
powerfully to its triumph. Albert the Great and St. Thomas, far from being
adversaries of St. Augustine, as they were reported to be, placed themselves in
his school, and while modifying certain theories, took over into their system
the doctrine of the African bishop. How many articles in the Summa
of St.
Thomas have no other object than to incorporate in theology this or the other
theory which was cherished by St. Augustine (to take only one example, that of
exemplar ideas in God). Hence, there was no longer any school strictly
Augustinian, because every school was such. They all eliminated certain special
points and retained the same veneration for the master.
From the third period of the fifteenth century to our days we see less of the special progress of philosophical Augustinism than certain tendencies of an exaggerated revival of Platonism. In the fifteenth century Bessarion (1472) and Marsilio Ficino (1499) used Augustine's name for the purpose of enthroning Plate in the Church and excluding Aristotle. In the seventeenth century it is impossible to deny certain resemblances between Cartesianism and the philosophy of St. Augustine. Malebranche was wrong in ascribing his own ontologism to the great Doctor, as were also many of his successors in the nineteenth century.
(2) Theological Augustinism
The history of Augustine's system of grace seems to blend almost indistinguishably with the progressive developments of this dogma. Here it must suffice, first, to enumerate the principal phases; secondly, to trace the general laws of development which mitigated Augustinism in the Church.
After the death of Augustine, a whole century of fierce contests (430-529)
ended in the triumph of fierce contests (430-529) ended in the triumph of
moderate Augustinism. In vain had Pope St. Celestine (431) sanctioned the
teachings of the Doctor of Hippo. The Semipelagians of the south of France could
not understand the predilection of God for the elect, and in order to attack the
works of St. Augustine they made use of the occasionally exaggerated formulæ of
St. Fulgentius, or of the real errors of certain isolated predestinationists, as,
for example, Lucidus, who was condemned in the Council of Arles (475). Happily,
Prosper of Aquitaine, by his moderation, and also the unknown author of De
Vocatione omnium gentium,
by his consoling thesis on the appeal addressed to
all, opened the way to an agreement. And finally, St. Cæsarius of Arles obtained
from Pope Felix IV a series of Capitula which were solemnly promulgated at
Orange, and gave their consecration to the triumph of Augustinism (529). In the
ninth century, a new victory was gained over the predestinationism of Gottschalk
in the assemblies of Savonniéres and Toucy (859-860). The doctrine of the Divine
will to save all men and the universality of redemption was thus consecrated by
the public teaching of the Church. In the Middle Ages these two truths are
developed by the great Doctors of the Church. Faithful to the principles of
Augustinism, they place in especial relief his theory on Divine Providence,
which prepares at its pleasure the determinations of the will by exterior events
and interior inspirations.
In the fourteenth century a strong current of predestinationism is evident.
Today it is admitted that the origin of this tendency goes back to Thomas
Bradwardin, a celebrated professor of Oxford, who died Archbishop of Canterbury
(1349), and whom the best critics, along with Loofs and Harnack, recognize to
have been the inspirer of Wyclif himself. His book De causâ Dei contra Pelagium
gave rise in Paris to disputes on Augustinian predetermination,
a word which,
it had been thought, was invented by Banes in the sixteenth century. In spite of
the opposition of theologians, the idea of absolute determinism in the name of
St. Augustine was adopted by Wyclif (1324-87), who formulated his universal
fatalism, the necessity of good for the elect and of evil for the rest. He
fancied that he found in the Augustinian doctrine the strange conception which
became for him a central doctrine that overthrew all morality and all
ecclesiastical, and even civil, government. According as one is predestined or
not, everything changes its nature. The same sins are mortal in the non-elect
which are venial in the predestined. The same acts of virtue are meritorious
predestined, even if he be actually a wicked man which are of no value in the
non-elect. The sacraments administered by one who is not predestined are always
invalid; more than that, no jurisdiction exists in a prelate, even a pope, if he
be not predestined. In the same way, there is no power, even civil or political,
in a prince who is not one of the elect, and no right of property in the sinner
or the non elect. Such is the basis on which Wyclif established the communism
which aroused the socialist mobs in England. It is incontestable that he was
fond of quoting Augustine as his authority; and his disciples, as we are assured
by Thomas Netter Waldensis (Doctrinale, I, xxxiv, § 5), were continually
boasting of the profound knowledge of their great Doctor, whom they called with
emphasis John of Augustine,
Shirley, in his introduction to Zizaniorum
Fasciculi,
has even pretended that the theories of Wyclif on God, on the
Incarnation, and even on property, were the purest Augustinian inspiration, but
even a superficial comparison, if this were the place to make it, would show how
baseless such an assertion is. In the sixteenth century the heritage of Wyclif
and Hus, his disciple, was always accepted in the name of Augustinism by the
leaders of the Reformation. Divine predestination from all eternity separating
the elect, who were to be snatched out of the mass of perdition, from the
reprobate who were destined to hell, as well as the irresistible impulse of God
drawing some to salvation and others to sin - such was the fundamental doctrine
of the Reformation. Calvinism even adopted a system which was logically more
consistent, but practically more revolting,
as Schaff puts it (St. Augustine,
p. 104), by which the decree of reprobation of the non-elect would be
independent of the fall of Adam and of original sin (Supralapsarianism). It was
certain that these harsh doctrines would bring their reaction, and in spite of
the severities of the Synod of Dordrecht, which it would be interesting to
compare with the Council of Trent in the matter of moderation, Arminianism
triumphed over the Calvinistic thesis.
We must note here that even Protestant critics, with a loyalty which does
them honour, have in these latter times vindicated Augustine from the false
interpretations of Calvin. Dorner, in his Gesch. der prot. Théologie,
had
already shown the instinctive repugnance of Anglican theologians to the horrible
theories of Calvin. W. Cunningham (Saint Austin, p. 82 sqq.) has very frankly
called attention to the complete doctrinal opposition on fundamental points
which exists between the Doctor of Hippo and the French Reformers. In the first
place, as regards the state of human nature, which is, according to Calvin,
totally depraved, for Catholics it is very difficult to grasp the Protestant
conception of original sin which, for Calvin and Luther, is not, as for us, the
moral degradation and the stain imprinted on the soul of every son of Adam by
the fault of the father which is imputable to each member of the family. It is
not the deprivation of grace and of all other super-natural gifts; it is not
even concupiscence, understood in the ordinary sense of the word, as the
struggle of base and selfish instincts against the virtuous tendencies of the
soul; it is a profound and complete subversion of human nature' it is the
physical alteration of the very substance of our soul. Our faculties,
understanding, and will, if not entirely destroyed, are at least mutilated,
powerless, and chained to evil. For the Reformers, original sin is not a sin, it
is the sin, and the permanent sin, living in us and causing a continual stream
of new sins to spring from our nature, which is radically corrupt and evil. For,
as our being is evil, every act of ours is equally evil. Thus, the Protestant
theologians do not ordinarily speak of the sins of mankind, but only of the sin,
which makes us what we are and defiles everything. Hence arose the paradox of
Luther: that even in an act of perfect charity a man sins mortally, because he
acts with a vitiated nature. Hence that other paradox: that this sin can never
be effaced, but remains entire, even after justification, although it will not
be any longer imputed; to efface it, it would be necessary to modify physically
this human being which is sin. Calvin, without going so far as Luther, has
nevertheless insisted on this total corruption. Let it stand, therefore, as an
indubitable truth which no engines can shake,
says he (Institution II, v, § 19),
that the mind of man is so entirely alienated from the righteousness of God
that he cannot conceive, desire, or design anything but what is weak, distorted,
foul, impure or iniquitous, that his heart is so thoroughly environed by sin
that it can breathe out nothing but corruption and rottenness; that if some men
occasionally make a show of goodness their mind is ever interwoven with
hypocrisy and deceit, their soul inwardly bound with the fetters of wickedness.
Now
, says Cunningham, this doctrine, whatever there may be to be said for it,
is not the doctrine of Saint Austin. He held that sin is the defect of a good
nature which retains elements of goodness, even in its most diseased and
corrupted state, and he gives no countenance, whatever to this modern opinion of
total depravity.
It is the same with Calvin's affirmation of the irresistible
action of God on the will. Cunningham shows that these doctrines are
irreconcilable with liberty and responsibility, whereas, on the contrary, St.
Austin is careful to attempt to harmonize the belief in God's omnipotence with
human responsibility
(St. Austin, p. 86). The Council of Trent was therefore
faithful to the true spirit of the African Doctor, and maintained pure
Augustinism in the bosom of the Church, by Its definitions against the two
opposite excesses. Against Pelagianism it reaffirmed original sin and the
absolute necessity of grace (Sess. VI, can. 2); against Protestant
predestinationism it proclaimed the freedom of man, with his double power of
resisting grace (posse dissentire si velit - Sess. VI, can. 4) and of doing
good or evil, even before embracing the Faith (can. 6 and 7).
In the seventeenth century Jansenism adopted, while modifying it, the Protestant conception of original sin and the state of fallen man. No more than Luther did the Jansenists admit the two orders, natural and supernatural. All the gifts which Adam had received immortality, knowledge, integrity, sanctifying grace - are absolutely required by the nature of man. Original sin is, therefore, again regarded as a profound alteration of human nature. From which the Jansenists conclude that the key to St. Augustine's system is to be found in the essential difference of the Divine government and of grace, before and after the Fall of Adam. Before the Fall Adam enjoyed complete liberty, and grace gave him the power of resisting or obeying; after the Fall there was no longer in men liberty properly so called; there was only spontaneity (libertas a coactione, and not libertas a necessitate). Grace, or delectation in the good, is essentially efficacious, and necessarily victorious once it is superior in degree to the opposite concupiscence. The struggle, which was prolonged for two centuries, led to a more profound study of the Doctor of Hippo and prepared the way for the definite triumph of Augustinism, but of an Augustinism mitigated in accordance with laws which we must now indicate.
(3) Laws which governed the mitigation of Augustinism
In spite of what Protestant critics may have said, the Church has always been faithful to the fundamental principles defended by Augustine against the Pelagians and Semipelagians, on original sin, the necessity and gratuity of grace, the absolute dependence on God for salvation. Nevertheless, great progress was made along the line of gradual mitigation. For it cannot be denied that the doctrine formulated at Trent, and taught by all our theologians, produces an impression of greater suavity and greater clarity than this or that passage in the works of St. Augustine. The causes of this softening down, and the successive phases of this progress were as follows:
- First, theologians began to distinguish more clearly between the natural
order and the supernatural, and hence the Fall of Adam no longer appeared as a
corruption of human nature in its constituent parts; it is the loss of the whole
order of supernatural elevation. St. Thomas (Summa, I:85:1) formulates the great
law of the preservation, in guilty Adam's children, of all the faculties in
their essential integrity:
Sin (even original) neither takes away nor diminishes the natural endowments.
Thus the most rigorist Thomists, Alvarez, Lemos, Contenson, agree with the great Doctor that the sin of Adam has not enfeebled (intrinsece) the natural moral forces of humanity. - Secondly, such consoling and fundamental truths as God's desire to save all
men, and the redeeming death of Christ which was really offered and accepted for
all peoples and all individuals - these truths, which Augustine never denied,
but which he left too much in the background and as it were hidden under the
terrible formulas of the doctrine of predestination, have been placed in the
full light, have been developed, and applied to infidel nations, and have at
last entered into the ordinary teaching of theology. Thus our Doctors, without
detracting in the least from the sovereignty and justice of God, have risen to
the highest idea of His goodness: that God so sincerely desires the salvation of
all as to give absolutely to all, immediately or mediately, the means necessary
for salvation, and always with the desire that man should consent to employ
those means. No one falls into hell except by his own fault. Even infidels will
be accountable for their infidelity. St. Thomas expresses the thought of all
when he says:
It is the common teaching that if a man born among the barbarous and infidel nations really does what lies in his power, God will reveal to him what is necessary for salvation, either by interior inspirations or by sending him a preacher of the Faith
(In Lib. II Sententiarum, dist. 23, Q. viii,a.4,ad 4am). We must not dissemble the fact that this law changes the whole aspect of Divine Providence, and that St. Augustine had left it too much in the shade, insisting only upon the other aspect of the problem: namely, that God, while making a sufficing appeal to all, is nevertheless not bound to choose always that appeal which shall in fact be efficacious and shall be accepted, provided that the refusal of consent be due to the obstinacy of the sinner's will and not to its lack of power. Thus the Doctors most eagerly approved the axiom, Facienti quod in se est Deus non denegat gratiam - God does not refuse grace to one who does what he can. - Thirdly, from principles taught by Augustine consequences have been drawn
which are clearly derived from them, but which he had not pointed out. Thus it
is incontestably a principle of St. Augustine that no one sins in an act which
he cannot avoid -
Quis enim peccat in eo quod caveri non potest?
This passage fromDe libero arbitrio
(III, xviii, n. 50) is anterior to the year 395; but far from retracting it he approves and explains it, in 415, in theDe naturâ et gratiâ
, lxvii, n. 80. From that pregnant principle theologians have concluded, first, that grace sufficient to conquer temptations never fails anyone, even an infidel; then, against the Jansenists, they have added that, to deserve its name of sufficient grace, it ought to give a real power which is complete even relatively to the actual difficulties. No doubt theologians have groped about, hesitated, even denied; but today there are very few who would dare not to recognize in St. Augustine the affirmation of the possibility of not sinning. - Fourthly, certain secondary assertions, which encumbered, but did not make part of the dogma, have been lopped off from the doctrine of Augustine. Thus the Church, which, with Augustine, has always denied entrance into Heaven to unbaptized children, has not adopted the severity of the great Doctor in condemning such children to bodily pains, however slight. And little by little the milder teaching of St. Thomas was to prevail in theology and was even to be vindicated against unjust censure when Pius VI condemned the pseudo-synod of Pistoja. At last Augustine's obscure formulæ were abandoned or corrected, so as to avoid regrettable confusions. Thus the expressions which seemed to identify original sin with concupiscence have given way to clearer formulæ without departing from the real meaning which Augustine sought to express.
Discussion, however, is not yet ended within the Church. On most of those
points which concern especially the manner of the Divine action Thomists and
Molinists disagree, the former holding out for an irresistible predetermination,
the latter maintaining, with Augustine, a grace whose infallible efficacy is
revealed by the Divine knowledge. But both of these views affirm the grace of
God and the liberty of man. The lively controversies aroused by the Concordia
of Molina (1588) and the long conferences de auxiliis held at Rome, before Popes
Clement VIII and Paul V, are well known. There is no doubt that a majority of
the theologian-consultors thought they discovered an opposition between Molina
and St. Augustine. But their verdict was not approved, and (what is of great
importance in the history of Augustinism) it is certain that they asked for the
condemnation of doctrines which are today universally taught in all the schools.
Thus, in the project of censure reproduced by Serry (Historia Congregationis de
Auxiliis,
append., p. 166) the first proposition is this: In statu naturæ
lapsæ potest homo, cum solo concursu generali Dei, efficere opus bonum morale,
quod in ordine ad finem hominis naturalem sit veræ virtutis opus, referendo
illud in Deum, sicut referri potest ac deberet in statu naturali
(In the state
of fallen nature man can with only the general concursus of God do a good moral
work which may be a work of true virtue with regard to the natural end of man by
referring it to God, as it can and ought to be referred in the natural state).
Thus they sought to condemn the doctrine held by all the Scholastics (with the
exception of Gregory of Rimini), and sanctioned since then by the condemnation
of Proposition lvii of Baius. For a long time it was said that the pope had
prepared a Bull to condemn Molina; but today we learn from an autograph document
of Paul V that liberty was left to the two schools until a new Apostolic
decision was given (Schneeman Controversiarum de Div. grat.,
1881, p. 289).
Soon after, a third interpretation of Augustinism was offered in the Church,
that of Noris, Belleli, and other partisans of moral predetermination. This
system has been called Augustinianism. To this school belong a number of
theologians who, with Thomassin, essayed to explain the infallible action of
grace without admitting either the scientia media of the Molinists or the
physical predetermination of the Thomists. A detailed study of this
interpretation of St. Augustine may be found in Vacant's Dictionnaire de
théologie catholique,
I, cols. 2485-2501; here I can only mention one very
important document, the last in which the Holy See has expressed its mind on the
various theories of theologians for reconciling grace and liberty. This is the
Brief of Benedict XIV (13 July, 1748) which declares that the three schools -
Thomist, Augustinian (Noris), and Molinist - have full right to defend their
theories. The Brief concludes with these words: This Apostolic See favours the
liberty of the schools; none of the systems proposed to reconcile the liberty of
man with the omnipotence of God has been thus far condemned (op. cit., co1.
2555).
In conclusion we must indicate briefly the official authority which the
Church attributes to St. Augustine in the questions of grace. Numerous and
solemn are the eulogies of St. Augustine's doctrine pronounced by the popes. For
instance, St. Gelasius I (1 November, 493), St. Hormisdas (13 August, 520),
Boniface II and the Fathers of Orange (529), John II (534), and many others. But
the most important document, that which ought to serve to interpret all the
others, because it precedes and inspires them, is the celebrated letter of St.
Celestine I (431), in which the pope guarantees not only the orthodoxy of
Augustine against his detractors, but also the great merit of his doctrine: So
great was his knowledge that my predecessors have always placed him in the rank
of the masters,
etc. This letter is accompanied by a series of ten dogmatic
capitula the origin of which is uncertain, but which have always been regarded,
at least since Pope Hormisdas, as expressing the faith of the Church. Now these
extracts from African councils and pontifical decisions end with this
restriction: As to the questions which are more profound and difficult, and
which have given rise to these controversies, we do not think it necessary to
impose the solution of them.
- In presence of these documents emanating from
so high a source, ought we to say that the Church has adopted all the teaching
of St. Augustine on grace so that it is never permissible to depart from that
teaching? Three answers have been given:
- For some, the authority of St. Augustine is absolute and irrefragable. The
Jansenists went so far as to formulate, with Havermans, this proposition,
condemned by Alexander VIII (7 December, 1690):
Ubi quis invenerit doctrinam in Augustino clare fundatam, illam absolute potest tenere et docere, non respiciendo ad ullam pontificis bullam
(Where one has found a doctrine clearly based on St. Augustine, he can hold and teach it absolutely without referring to any pontifical Bull). This is inadmissible. None of the pontifical approbations has a meaning so absolute, and the capitula make an express reservation for the profound and difficult questions. The popes themselves have permitted a departure from the thought of St. Augustine in the matter of the lot of children dying without baptism (BullAuctorem Fidei
, 28 August, 1794). - Others again have concluded that the eulogies in question are merely vague formulæ leaving full liberty to withdraw from St. Augustine and to blame him on every point. Thus Launoy, Richard Simon, and others have maintained that Augustine had been in error on the very gist of the problem, and had really taught predestinationism. But that would imply that for fifteen centuries the Church took as its guide an adversary of its faith.
- We must conclude, with the greater number of theologians, that Augustine has a real normative authority, hedged about, however, with reserves and wise limitations. In the capital questions which constitute the faith of the Church in those matters the Doctor of Hippo is truly the authoritative witness of tradition; for example, on the existence of original sin, the necessity of grace, at least for every salutary act; the gratuitousness of the gift of God which precedes all merit of man because it is the cause of it; the predilection for the elect and, on the other hand, the liberty of man and his responsibility for his transgressions. But the secondary problems, concerning the mode rather than the fact, are left by the Church to the prudent study of theologians. Thus all schools unite in a great respect for the assertions of St. Augustine.
At present this attitude of fidelity and respect is all the more remarkable
as Protestants, who were formerly so bitter in defending the predestination of
Calvin, are today almost unanimous in rejecting what they themselves call the
boldest defiance ever given to reason and conscience
(Grétillat, Dogmatique
,
III, p. 329). Schleiermacher, it is true, maintains it, but he adds to it the
Origenist theory of universal salvation by the final restoration of all
creatures, and he is followed in this by Farrar Lobstein, Pfister, and others.
The Calvinist dogma is today, especially in England, altogether abandoned, and
often replaced by pure Pelagianism (Beyschlag). But among Protestant critics the
best are drawing near to the Catholic interpretation of St. Augustine, as, for
example, Grétillat, in Switzerland, and Stevens, Bruce, and Mozley (On the
Augustinian Doctrine of Predestination), in England. Sanday (Romans, p. 50) also
declares the mystery to be unfathomable for man yet solved by God: And so our
solution of the problem of Free-will, and of the problems of history and of
individual salvation, must finally lie in the full acceptance and realization of
what is implied by the infinity and the omniscience of God.
These concluding
words recall the true system of Augustine and permit us to hope that at least on
this question there may be a union of the two Churches in a wise Augustinism.
Heiligenlexikon als USB-Stick oder als DVD
Unterstützung für das Ökumenische Heiligenlexikon
Artikel kommentieren / Fehler melden
Suchen bei amazon: Bücher über Catholic Encyclopedia - Teaching of St. Augustine of Hippo
Wikipedia: Artikel über Catholic Encyclopedia - Teaching of St. Augustine of Hippo
Fragen? - unsere FAQs antworten!
Impressum - Datenschutzerklärung
korrekt zitieren: Artikel
Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet das Ökumenische Heiligenlexikon in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über https://d-nb.info/1175439177 und https://d-nb.info/969828497 abrufbar.