Hinweise zur Catholic Encyclopedia
St. Albertus Magnus
Known as Albert the Great; scientist, philosopher, and theologian, born c.
1206; died at Cologne, 15 November 1280. He is called the Great
, and Doctor
Universalis
(Universal Doctor), in recognition of his extraordinary genius and
extensive knowledge, for he was proficient in every branch of learning
cultivated in his day, and surpassed all his contemporaries, except perhaps
Roger Bacon (1214-94), in the knowledge of nature. Ulrich Engelbert, a
contemporary, calls him the wonder and the miracle of his age: Vir in omni
scientia adeo divinus, ut nostri temporis stupor et miraculum congrue vocari
possit
(De summo bono, tr. III, iv).
I. LIFE
Albert, eldest son of the Count of Bollstädt, was born at Lauingen, Swabia,
in the year 1205 or 1206, though many historians give it as 1193. Nothing
certain is known of his primary or preparatory education, which was received
either under the paternal roof or in a school of the neighbourhood. As a youth
he was sent to pursue his studies at the University of Padua; that city being
chosen either because his uncle resided there, or because Padua was famous for
its culture of the liberal arts, for which the young Swabian had a special
predilection. The date of this journey to Padua cannot be accurately determined.
In the year 1223 he joined the Order of St. Dominic, being attracted by the
preaching of Blessed Jordan of Saxony second Master General of the Order.
Historians do not tell us whether Albert's studies were continued at Padua,
Bologna, Paris, or Cologne. After completing his studies he taught theology at
Hildesheim, Freiburg (Breisgau), Ratisbon, Strasburg, and Cologne. He was in the
convent of Cologne, interpreting Peter Lombard's Book of the Sentences
, when,
in 1245, he was ordered to repair to Paris. There he received the Doctor's
degree in the university which, above all others, was celebrated as a school of
theology. It was during this period ofreaching at Cologne and Paris that he
counted amongst his hearers St. Thomas Aquinas, then a silent, thoughtful youth,
whose genius he recognized and whose future greatness he foretold. The disciple
accompanied his master to Paris in 1245, and returned with him, in 1248, to the
new Studium Generale of Cologne, in which Albert was appointed Regent, whilst
Thomas became second professor and Magister Studentium (Master of Students). In
1254 Albert was elected Provincial of his Order in Germany. He journeyed to Rome
in 1256, to defend the Mendicant Orders against the attacks of William of St.
Amour, whose book, De novissimis temporum periculis
, was condemned by Pope
Alexander IV, on 5 October, 1256. During his sojourn in Rome Albert filled the
office of Master of the Sacred Palace (instituted in the time of St. Dominic),
and preached on the Gospel of St. John and the Canonical Epistles. He resigned
the office of Provincial in 1257 in order to devote himself to study and to
teaching. At the General Chapter of the Dominicans held at Valenciennes in 1250,
with St. Thomas Aquinas and Peter of Tarentasia (afterwards Pope Innocent V), he
drew up rules for the direction of studies, and for determining the system of
graduation, in the Order. In the year 1260 he was appointed Bishop of Ratisbon.
Humbert de Romanis, Master General of the Dominicans, being loath to lose the
services of the great Master, endeavoured to prevent the nomination, but was
unsuccessful. Albert governed the diocese until 1262, when, upon the acceptance
of his resignation, he voluntarily resumed the duties of a professor in the
Studium at Cologne. In the year 1270 he sent a memoir to Paris to aid St. Thomas
in combating Siger de Brabant and the Averroists. This was his second special
treatise against the Arabian commentator, the first having been written in 1256,
under the title De Unitate Intellectus Contra Averroem
. He was called by Pope
Gregory X to attend the Council of Lyons (1274) in the deliberations of which he
took an active part. The announcement of the death of St. Thomas at Fossa Nuova,
as he was proceeding to the Council, was a heavy blow to Albert, and he declared
that The Light of the Church
had been extinguished. It was but natural that he
should have grown to love his distinguished, saintly pupil, and it is said that
ever afterwards he could not restrain his tears whenever the name of St. Thomas
was mentioned. Something of his old vigour and spirit returned in 1277 when it
was announced that Stephen Tempier and others wished to condemn the writings of
St. Thomas, on the plea that they were too favourable to the unbelieving
philosophers, and he journeyed to Paris to defend the memory of his disciple.
Some time after 1278 (in which year he drew up his testament) he suffered a
lapse of memory; his strong mind gradually became clouded; his body, weakened by
vigils, austerities, and manifold labours, sank under the weight of years. He
was beatified by Pope Gregory XV in 1622; his feast is celebrated on the 15th of
November. The Bishops of Germany, assembled at Fulda in September, 1872, sent to
the Holy See a petition for his canonization; he was finally canonized in 1931.
II. WORKS
Two editions of Albert's complete works (Opera Omnia) have been published;
one at Lyons in 1651, in twenty-one folio volumes, edited by Father Peter Jammy,
O.P., the other at Paris (Louis Vivès), 1890-99, in thirty-eight quarto volumes,
published under the direction of the Abbé Auguste Borgnet, of the diocese of
Reims. Paul von Loë gives the chronology of Albert's writings the Analecta
Bollandiada
(De Vita et scriptis B. Alb. Mag., XIX, XX, and XXI). The logical
order is given by P. Mandonnet, O.P., in Vacant's Dictionnaire de théologie
catholique
. The following list indicates the subjects of the various treatises,
the numbers referring to the volumes of Borgnet's edition. Logic: seven
treatises (I. 2). Physical Sciences: Physicorum
(3); De Coelo et Mundo
, De
Generatione et Corruptione
. Meteororum
(4); Mineralium
(5); De Natura
locorum
, De passionibus aeris
(9). Biological: De vegetabilibus et plantis
(10) De animalibus
(11-12); De motibus animalium
, De nutrimento et
nutribili
, De aetate
, De morte et vita
, De spiritu et respiratione
(9).
Psychological: De Anima
(5); De sensu et sensato
, De Memoria, et
reminiscentia
, De somno et vigilia
, De natura et origine animae
, De
intellectu et intelligibili
, De unitate intellectus
(9). The foregoing
subjects, with the exception of Logic, are treated compendiously in the
Philosophia pauperum
(5). Moral and Political: Ethicorum
(7); Politocorum
(8). Metaphysical:
(38);
Metaphysicorum
(6); De causis et processu universitatis
(10). Theological: Commentary on the works of Denis the Aereopagite
(14);
Commentary on the Sentences of the Lombard
(25-30); Summa Theologiae
(31-33);
Summa de creaturis
(34-35); De sacramento Eucharistiae
(38); Super
evangelium missus est
(37). Exegetical: Commentaries on the Psalms and
Prophets
(15-19); Commentaries on the Gospels
(20-24); On the Apocalypse
(38). Sermons (13). The Quindecim problemata contra Averroistas
was edited by
Mandonnet in his Siger de Brabant
(Freiburg, 1899). The authenticity of the
following works is not established: De apprehensione
(5); Speculum
astronomicum
(5); De alchimia
(38); Scriptum super arborem AristotelisParadisus animae
(37); Liber de Adhaerendo Deo
(37); De Laudibus B.
Virginis
(36); Biblia Mariana
(37).
III. INFLUENCE
The influence exerted by Albert on the scholars of his own day and on those
of subsequent ages was naturally great. His fame is due in part to the fact that
he was the forerunner, the guide and master of St. Thomas Aquinas, but he was
great in his own name, his claim to distinction being recognized by his
contemporaries and by posterity. It is remarkable that this friar of the Middle
Ages, in the midst of his many duties as a religious, as provincial of his order,
as bishop and papal legate, as preacher of a crusade, and while making many
laborious journeys from Cologne to Paris and Rome, and frequent excursions into
different parts of Germany, should have been able to compose a veritable
encyclopedia, containing scientific treatises on almost every subject, and
displaying an insight into nature and a knowledge of theology which surprised
his contemporaries and still excites the admiration of learned men in our own
times. He was, in truth, a Doctor Universalis. Of him it in justly be said: Nil
tetigit quod non ornavit; and there is no exaggeration in the praises of the
modern critic who wrote: Whether we consider him as a theologian or as a
philosopher, Albert was undoubtedly one of the most extraordinary men of his age;
I might say, one of the most wonderful men of genius who appeared in past times
(Jourdain, Recherches Critiques). Philosophy, in the days of Albert, was a
general science embracing everything that could be known by the natural powers
of the mind; physics, mathematics, and metaphysics. In his writings we do not,
it is true, find the distinction between the sciences and philosophy which
recent usage makes. It will, however, be convenient to consider his skill in the
experimental sciences, his influence on scholastic philosophy, his theology.
IV. ALBERT AND THE EXPERIMENTAL SCIENCES
It is not surprising that Albert should have drawn upon the sources of
information which his time afforded, and especially upon the scientific writings
of Aristotle. Yet he says: The aim of natural science is not simply to accept
the statements [narrata] of others, but to investigate the causes that are at
work in nature
(De Miner., lib. II, tr. ii, i). In his treatise on plants he
lays down the principle: Experimentum solum certificat in talibus (Experiment is
the only safe guide in such investigations). (De Veg., VI, tr. ii, i). Deeply
versed as he was in theology, he declares: In studying nature we have not to
inquire how God the Creator may, as He freely wills, use His creatures to work
miracles and thereby show forth His power: we have rather to inquire what Nature
with its immanent causes can naturally bring to pass
(De Coelo et Mundo, I, tr.
iv, x). And though, in questions of natural science, he would prefer Aristotle
to St. Augustine (In 2, Sent. dist. 13, C art. 2), he does not hesitate to
criticize the Greek philosopher. Whoever believes that Aristotle was a god,
must also believe that he never erred. But if one believe that Aristotle was a
man, then doubtless he was liable to error just as we are.
(Physic. lib. VIII,
tr. 1, xiv). In fact Albert devotes a lengthy chapter to what he calls the
errors of Aristotle
(Sum. Theol. P. II, tr. i, quaest. iv). In a word, his
appreciation of Aristotle is critical. He deserves credit not only for bringing
the scientific teaching of the Stagirite to the attention of medieval scholars,
but also for indicating the method and the spirit in which that teaching was to
be received. Like his contemporary, Roger Bacon (1214-94), Albert was an
indefatigable student of nature, and applied himself energetically to the
experimental sciences with such remarkable success that he has been accused of
neglecting the sacred sciences (Henry of Ghent, De scriptoribus ecclesiasticis,
II, x). Indeed, many legends have been circulated which attribute to him the
power of a magician or sorcerer. Dr. Sighart (Albertus Magnus) examined these
legends, and endeavoured to sift the truth from false or exaggerated stories.
Other biographers content themselves with noting the fact that Albert's
proficiency in the physical sciences was the foundation on which the fables were
constructed. The truth lies between the two extremes. Albert was assiduous in
cultivating the natural sciences; he was an authority on physics, geography,
astronomy, mineralogy, chemistry (alchimia), zoölogy, physiology, and even
phrenology. On all these subjects his erudition was vast, and many of his
observations are of permanent value. Humboldt pays a high tribute to his
knowledge of physical geography (Cosmos, II, vi). Meyer writes (Gesch. der
Botanik): No botanist who lived before Albert can be compared with him, unless
it be Theophrastus, with whom he was not acquainted; and after him none has
painted nature in such living colours, or studied it so profoundly, until the
time of Conrad, Gesner, and Cesalpini. All honour, then, to the man who made
such astonishing progress in the science of nature as to find no one, I will not
say to surpass, but even to equal him for the space of three centuries.
The
list of his published works is sufficient vindication from the charge of
neglecting theology and the Sacred Scriptures. On the other hand, he expressed
contempt for everything that savoured of enchantment or the art of magic: Non
approbo dictum Avicennae et Algazel de fascinatione, quia credo quod non nocet
fascinatio, nec nocere potest ars magica, nec facit aliquid ex his quae timentur
de talibus
(See Quétif, I, 167). That he did not admit the possibility of
making gold by alchemy or the use of the philosopher's stone, is evident from
his own words: Art alone cannot produce a substantial form
. (Non est probatum
hoc quod educitur de plumbo esse aurum, eo quod sola ars non potest dare formam
substantialem - De Mineral., lib. II, dist. 3).
Roger Bacon and Albert proved to the world that the Church is not opposed to
the study of nature, that faith and science may go hand in hand; their lives and
their writings emphasize the importance of experiment and investigation. Bacon
was indefatigable and bold in investigating; at times, too, his criticism was
sharp. But of Albert he said: Studiosissimus erat, et vidit infinita, et habuit
expensum, et ideo multa potuit colligere in pelago auctorum infinito
(Opera, ed.
Brewer, 327). Albert respected authority and traditions, was prudent in
proposing the results of his investigations, and hence contributed far more
than Bacon did to the advancement of science in the thirteenth century
(Turner,
Hist. of Phil.). His method of treating the sciences was historical and critical.
He gathered into one vast encyclopedia all that was known in his day, and then
expressed his own opinions, principally in the form of commentaries on the works
of Aristotle. Sometimes, however, he hesitates, and does not express his own
opinion, probably because he feared that his theories, which were advanced
for
those times, would excite surprise and occasion unfavourable comment. Dicta
peripateticorum, prout melius potui exposui: nec aliquis in eo potest
deprehendere quid ego ipse sentiam in philosophia naturali
(De Animalibus,
circa finem). In Augusta Theodosia Drane's excellent work on Christian Schools
and Scholars
(419 sqq.) there are some interesting remarks on a few scientific
views of Albert, which show how much he owed to his own sagacious observation of
natural phenomena, and how far he was in advance of his age …
In speaking
of the British Isles, he alluded to the commonly received idea that another
Island - Tile, or Thule - existed in the Western Ocean, uninhabitable by reason
of its frightful clime, but which
, he says, has perhaps not yet been visited
by man. Albert gives an elaborate demonstration of the sphericity of the earth;
and it has been pointed out that his views on this subject led eventually to the
discovery of America (cf. Mandonnet, in Revue Thomiste
, I, 1893; 46-64,
200-221).
V. ALBERT AND SCHOLASTIC PHILOSOPHY
More important than Albert's development of the physical sciences was his
influence on the study of philosophy and theology. He, more than any one of the
great scholastics preceding St. Thomas, gave to Christian philosophy and
theology the form and method which, substantially, they retain to this day. In
this respect he was the forerunner and master of St. Thomas, who excelled him,
however, in many qualities required in a perfect Christian Doctor. In marking
out the course which other followed, Albert shared the glory of being a pioneer
with Alexander of Hales (d. 1245), whose Summa Theologiae
was the first
written after all the works of Aristotle had become generally known at Paris.
Their application of Aristotelean methods and principles to the study of
revealed doctrine gave to the world the scholastic system which embodies the
reconciliation of reason and Orthodox faith. After the unorthodox Averroes,
Albert was the chief commentator on the works of, Aristotle, whose writings he
studied most assiduously, and whose principles he adopted, in order to
systematize theology, by which was meant a scientific exposition and defence of
Christian doctrine. The choice of Aristotle as a master excited strong
opposition. Jewish and Arabic commentaries on the works of the Stagirite had
given rise to so many errors in the eleventh, twelfth and thirteenth centuries
that for several years (1210-25) the study of Aristotle's Physics and
Metaphysics was forbidden at Paris. Albert, however, knew that Averroes, Abelard,
Amalric, and others had drawn false doctrines from the writings of the
Philosopher; he knew, moreover, that it would have been impossible to stem the
tide of enthusiasm in favour of philosophical studies; and so he resolved to
purify the works of Aristotle from Rationalism, Averroism, Pantheism, and other
errors, and thus compel pagan philosophy to do service in the cause of revealed
truth. In this he followed the canon laid down by St. Augustine (II De Doct.
Christ., xl), who declared that truths found in the writings of pagan
philosophers were to be adopted by the defenders of the true faith, while their
erroneous opinions were to be abandoned, or explained in a Christian sense. (See
St. Thomas, Summa Theol., I, Q. lxxxiv, a. 5.) All inferior (natural) sciences
should be the servants (ancillae) of Theology, which is the superior and the
mistress (ibid., 1 P., tr. 1, quaest. 6). Against the rationalism of Abelard and
his followers Albert pointed out the distinction between truths naturally
knowable and mysteries (e.g. the Trinity and the Incarnation) which cannot known
without revelation (ibid., 1 P., tr. III, quaest. 13). We have seen that he
wrote two treatises against Averroism, which destroyed individual immortality
and individual responsibility, by teaching that there is but one rational soul
for all men. Pantheism was refuted along with Averroism when the true doctrine
on Universals, the system known as moderate Realism, was accepted by the
scholastic philosophers. This doctrine Albert based upon the Distinction of the
universal ante rem (an idea or archetype in the mind of God), in re (existing or
capable of existing in many individuals), and post rem (as a concept abstracted
by the mind, and compared with the individuals of which it can be predicated).
Universale duobus constituitur, natura, scilicet cui accidit universalitas, et
respectu ad multa. qui complet illam in natura universalis
(Met., lib. V, tr.
vi, cc. v, vi). A.T. Drane (Mother Raphael, O.S.D.) gives a remarkable
explanation of these doctrines (op. cit. 344-429). Though follower of Aristotle,
Albert did not neglect Plato. Scias quod non perficitur homo in philosophia,
nisi scientia duarum philosophiarum, Aristotelis et Platonis (Met., lib. I, tr.
v, c. xv). It is erroneous to say that he was merely the
Ape
(simius) of
Aristotle. In the knowledge of Divine things faith precedes the understanding of
Divine truth, authority precedes reason (I Sent., dist. II, a. 10); but in
matters that can be naturally known a philosopher should not hold an opinion
which he is not prepared to defend by reason ibid., XII; Periherm., 1, I, tr. l,
c. i). Logic, according to Albert, was a preparation for philosophy teaching how
we should use reason in order to pass from the known to the unknown: Docens
qualiter et per quae devenitur per notum ad ignoti notitiam
(De praedicabilibus,
tr. I, c. iv). Philosophy is either contemplative or practical. Contemplative
philosophy embraces physics, mathematics, and metaphysics; practical (moral)
plilosophy is monastic (for the individual), domestic (for the family), or
political (for the state, or society). Excluding physics, now a special study,
authors in our times still retain the old scholastic division of philosophy into
logic, metaphysics (general and special), and ethics.
VI. ALBERT'S THEOLOGY
In theology Albert occupies a place between Peter Lombard, the Master of the
Sentences, and St. Thomas Aquinas. In systematic order, in accuracy and
clearness he surpasses the former, but is inferior to his own illustrious
disciple. His Summa Theologiae
marks an advance beyond the custom of his time
in the scientific order observed, in the elimination of useless questions, in
the limitation of arguments and objections; there still remain, however, many of
the impedimenta, hindrances, or stumbling blocks, which St. Thomas considered
serious enough to call for a new manual of theology for the use of beginners -
ad eruditionem incipientium, as the Angelic Doctor modestly remarks in the
prologue of his immortal Summa
. The mind of the Doctor Universalis was so
filled with the knowledge of many things that he could not always adapt his
expositions of the truth to the capacity of novices in the science of theology.
He trained and directed a pupil who gave the world a concise, clear, and perfect
scientific exposition and defence of Christian Doctrine; under God, therefore,
we owe to Albertus Magnus the Summa Theologica
of St. Thomas.
Heiligenlexikon als USB-Stick oder als DVD
Unterstützung für das Ökumenische Heiligenlexikon
Artikel kommentieren / Fehler melden
Suchen bei amazon: Bücher über Catholic Encyclopedia - St. Albertus Magnus
Wikipedia: Artikel über Catholic Encyclopedia - St. Albertus Magnus
Fragen? - unsere FAQs antworten!
Impressum - Datenschutzerklärung
korrekt zitieren: Artikel
Die Deutsche Nationalbibliothek verzeichnet das Ökumenische Heiligenlexikon in der Deutschen Nationalbibliografie; detaillierte bibliografische Daten sind im Internet über https://d-nb.info/1175439177 und https://d-nb.info/969828497 abrufbar.